Search This Blog

Showing posts with label long-term exploration. Show all posts
Showing posts with label long-term exploration. Show all posts

Thursday, June 23, 2011

LIFE IN SPACE: THE COMPLETE STORY?

Chapter 6L

LIFE IN SPACE: THE COMPLETE STORY?

Astrobiology and what I have called space biology proper do not exhaust the possibilities that space offers to the life sciences. Those possibilities extend to many areas in which our understanding of life may have profound consequences for our interaction with nature. I would like to conclude this chapter by considering briefly three novel areas of investigation.

The first may be called planetary biology, or perhaps global biology. So far I have discussed our attempts to understand micro-organisms, plants, and animals. But we also wish to understand the living environment as a whole and in relation to the other components of the global environment. Planetary biology attempts to achieve this by means of interdisciplinary research that makes extensive use of space techniques for atmospheric sampling and remote sensing. From the remarks made in Chapter 4 it is clear that the study of the role of bacteria and plants in the global environment fits in nicely with the aims of planetary science. Planetary biology expands the scope of investigation and makes the relationship to general planetary science all that more evident. One of its initial aims is to trace the flow of nitrogen and sulfur in the marine environment off the coast of California, and to determine the mechanisms by which different compounds of these elements are converted into others.[1] The eventual goal of this new field is quite ambitious. In Harold Klein's words, it is "to treat the planet as an ecosystem and try to understand the laws of this ecosystem."[2]

A second area of investigation involves the construction of closed environments in space. Until now we have not built any really closed environments up there -- natural wastes are thrown into space, not recycled as on the Earth, oxygen is lost to the vacuum, and so on.[3] Furthermore, the balance of those environments is maintained by artificial means. Whether we can ever built living closed environments in space is a matter of controversy. Indeed, at this time we cannot even determine the minimum size required for a naturally self-sustaining environment amenable to Earth life. But in trying to build one we may learn much. In fact, even artificially closed environments may teach us valuable lessons about terrestrial ecology.

There are several obstacles that limit severely the knowledge we can obtain about an ecological system. One of them is that the amount of variables involved, most of which are interrelated, is simply unmanageable. And even when this obstacle is overcome, the victory seldom lasts long. Normally, a model of a system accounts for changes in one part of the system by changing the amount of reaction in other parts. More sophisticated models may go as far as predicting the rate of such reaction. The problem is that, when confronted with different circumstances, organisms sometimes change not just the amount and rate but the modality of reaction. This problem is illustrated by two examples from a report of the National Academy of Sciences entitled Life Beyond the Earth's Environment: "...many bacteria will use available nitrogen if it is present but in its absence become fixers of nitrogen from the air. Brown hydra in competition with green hydra will, in the presence of abundant food, eat their competitors, and in the absence of abundant food, will float away to some new location leaving the area to the green hydra alone."[4]

Another problem is that a complete description of an ecosystem often requires that we count the numbers of each kind of organism in order to ascertain what it contributes to the flux of matter and energy of that ecosystem. But such counting, for example of worms in the soil, in many cases destroys the ecosystem we are merely trying to describe.

A suggestion for getting around these problems is that we test models of the system in closed versions of it. These models would not attempt to represent every element of the system -- which would be practically impossible -- but would be based instead on a list of the species present and on the roles played by the species presumed to dominate the system. The suggestion is that we build closed environments in accordance with one such model, and then partition them in a variety of ways. We can learn from the interruptions in the normal flows and cycles of the system what its crucial factors are. By disturbing or interrupting the cycle of nutrients, for example, many species may starve while their food accumulates elsewhere, and others may be poisoned by the concentration of toxic wastes that normally would have been washed away. Of course, these partitions do not only take away from the system, in some cases they add to it; just as a dam that interrupts the flow of a river creates a habitat favorable to a variety of organisms that would have been at a disadvantage otherwise.

Intelligent manipulation of this ecology of failure offers the prospect of many exciting questions and experiments. But on Earth there are two serious limitations. One is that the only completely closed system is the Earth itself, which, though open to energy, is relatively closed to matter. Partial closure is of course satisfactory for many investigations, but in some cases we may need greater experimental control. Another limitation is that some closures may be dangerous or undesirable (they may produce very toxic substances, for example). Space offers an opportunity to achieve perfect closure in many investigations that cry out for it; it also permits us to carry out some of the most dangerous experiments in capsules safely isolated from our home planet.

An apparent limitation of space is that larger and richer environments cannot be easily recreated. But there is a sense in which this limitation becomes an advantage. An increased manned presence in space means a greater complexity of man-made habitats, perhaps with a serious attempt to create space agriculture. But this would automatically require that as the ecosystem gets larger we learn more and more about what the crucial flows and cycles are and what it takes to maintain them. A lunar base, for example, can be viewed as an experiment to determine the degree to which environmental sufficiency can be achieved. And a Martian colony may be in a good position to experiment with a variety of environments for agriculture, since the red planet is rich in resources and the colonists may thus have many choices in the composition of such environments. Gerard O'Neill's space colonies may have an even greater potential.

A third area of promise is the invention of new tools to investigate the basic levels of organisms. This point seldom receives the attention it deserves. The absence of gravity permits the development of experimental techniques that are either very difficult or plain impossible on the surface of the planet. I will mention a few ideas that have been suggested over the years, just to catch the flavor of the possibilities.

The technique of electrophoresis, which was described in Chapter 2, can become a useful tool for the production of pure drugs. But its real potential may be found in research instead. For example, our metabolic processes are controlled by about 2,000 enzymes, of which as many as one hundred are mixtures of isozymes. With electrophoresis, we can separate and study those isozymes. If nothing else we can vastly improve our diagnostic skills in matters concerning imbalances and disorders of the human body.

And I think there is reason to believe that this use of electrophoresis in space may herald a new generation of analytical tools for biologists and medical researchers. And that reason is simply that by removing gravity we may not only gain much in purity but also take advantage of the fine operation of electric currents. Some of this fine operation already pays dividends on Earth. Using weak pulsed electric fields, for instance, it is possible to induce cells to fuse, a technique that leads to very unusual new cells. It can be used, among other things, to fuse tumor cells with the spleen cells that produce the specific antibodies that could destroy the tumor if there were only enough of them. The value of one of these fused cells (hybridomas) is that it will make many copies of itself (clones). And all of these copies will produce the same antibody of the original spleen cell, but now in large amounts, we hope, to get rid of the tumor once and for all. I do not know whether this very technique will prove feasible in space.[5] But others kindred to it may find in the advantages of space (purity, effective use of weak currents) the right spark to ignite a new explosion in biomedical research.

Many tools for medical research, and many new medical technologies may come from physics instead. According to an article by John Tierney:

The Russians invented an air scrubber using strong electric fields and cold-plasma chambers to prevent biological contamination of the air in the MIR space station. Now the French-based firm AirlnSpace, with support from the European Space Agency, have refined the Russian invention to create the portable “Inmunair.” According to the firm’s general manager, the system successfully screened anthrax and small-pox substitutes in laboratory tests.[6]

These three areas are mere examples. I have neither the expertise nor the imagination to evaluate all the promise of space biology. Suffice it to say, for now, that space biology is in a position to ask not only new questions but also new kinds of questions. In this, like the rest of space science, it fulfills the function of preserving the dynamic character of science. Some of space biology, the search for origins in particular, merits its pursuit as a main goal. Space biology proper, as I have called it, is in its theoretical and experimental infancy, and will probably have to ride as a passenger of other space undertakings. Nevertheless I have given reasons why it is worth supporting in its own right. For the time being, it can be considered as one of the benefits that come to us from the general exploration of space.



[1] For example, to what extent is dymethyl sulfide produced by marine algae?

[2] Harold Klein, "The Biological Sciences and NASA," NASA Advisory Council Talk, May 1983, p.5 of the text.

[3] For a discussion of these issues see Life Beyond the Earth's Environment, a report of the Space Science Board of the National Academy of Sciences, 1979 (section in ecology, pp. 105-132); R.M. Mason, J.L. Carden, eds., Controlled Ecological Life Support System: Research and Development Guidelines, NASA CP-2232, 1982; B. Moore III and R.D. MacElroy, Controlled Ecological Life Support System: Biological Problems, NASA CP-2233, 1982; and B. Moore III, R.A. Wharton, R.D. MacElroy, eds., Controlled Ecological Life Support Systems: First Principal Investigators Meeting, NASA CP-2247, 1982.

[4] Life Beyond the Earth's Environment, ibid., p.111.

[5] There are three problems with this technique as a weapon against cancer. One is the difficulty in the formation of hybridomas. In this, weak currents offer some advantages over competing technologies. My guess is that these advantages would be even more apparent in microgravity. A second problem is the stability of the hybridomas. In this, the record of microgravity experimentation should offer some encouragement. The third problem is the selection of the appropriate spleen cell to fuse with the tumor. In this, space does not offer special advantages, unless we consider the possibility of refined techniques of separation and identification.

[6] John Tierney, “Outer Space on Earth: NASA Should Try It,” reprinted in Detroit Free Press, August 2, 2005, p. 7A. Tierney’s derogatory comments are limited to the Space Shuttle. He does believe that much worthwhile scientific exploration can be done otherwise.

Saturday, January 16, 2010

Long-term exploration, SETI, space war

Dimming of Starlight

Ch. 1C


Space scientists, who may be generally sympathetic to the main theses of this book, are nevertheless deeply divided on the question of how best to explore space. Some claim that exploring with humans is frightfully expensive and dangerous, that the Space Shuttle has set back the cause of exploration, and that continuing to favor astronauts over robot spacecraft will set it back even further. And they are indeed correct – in the short run. I argue in Chapter 7 that a measured increment of the human presence in space will eventually lead to even greater opportunities for all the space sciences. I also point out how the proposed colonization of other planets, the mining of the asteroids, and the expansion into the outer solar system, and perhaps the galaxy, may secure the survival of the human species. Of course, such fanciful proposals may be little more than far-fetched dreams, but those dreams begin to pull us away from our mother planet, and as they color our perception of space exploration they influence its direction. Even more fanciful, although of special scientific and philosophical interest, are the heated debates about relativistic starships and faster-than-light travel.

Perhaps no aspect of space exploration has been as controversial as the search for extraterrestrial intelligence (SETI). For some it has been a noble calling, for others the most ridiculous waste of money and effort. The critics won the day in Congress when NASA was forced to drop SETI altogether many years ago, although private donations and platoons of volunteers have kept the search going. As we will see in Chapter 8, many of the arguments for and against the existence of extraterrestrial intelligence are based on what Carl Sagan called the “Principle of Mediocrity” (that the Copernican revolution has taught that there is nothing special about the Earth or its place in the universe). But, as I will argue, such a principle does not stand up to criticism. We have no good reasons for optimism or pessimism on this matter: the most reasonable position is agnosticism.

This is not to say that SETI is a worthless enterprise. For example, the problem of how we might communicate with extraterrestrial civilizations, if there are any, teaches us a few things about how we understand the world and ourselves. It is often thought that advanced species will have discovered many of the fundamental laws of physics, chemistry, and so on; otherwise they could not make the attempt to communicate across the vastness of interstellar space. But since the laws of nature are (presumably) the same everywhere, and since they are expressed in mathematics, all advanced species will have things in common that can serve as the basis of communication. According to this conventional wisdom, then, there must be intellectual convergence between highly intelligent species, just as there is convergence of form between fishes and dolphins.

But how can we support this assumption of convergence? Evolutionary history is made up of millions of contingencies. It would be practically impossible for life to evolve in other worlds along the same paths it has followed on Earth. We thus face an unpleasant consequence: a different evolutionary history may produce different brains – different ways, that is, of perceiving the environment and of putting those perceptions together. And those are the brains that will one day develop science. It is thus plausible to suggest that those brains will operate with mental categories different from ours, and that alien science and mathematics may also differ from ours. Discussing the assumption of convergence will thus involve us in the philosophical problem of whether we discover or invent science.

Another idea whose discussion leads to a better understanding of living beings is the suggestion by Freeman Dyson and others that we should use von Neumann self-reproducing machines to colonize the galaxy. I argue, also in Chapter 8, that the very idea of such technology is based on the mistaken metaphor of the genome as a computer program. The speculations by Robert Zubrin that nanotechnology will allow us to get around the overwhelming obstacles to self-reproducing machines do not get very far either, for some of the most fanciful claims made about nanotechnology are also without justification.[i]

Many interesting issues come up in the details of practically all the fields of exploration discussed in this book. In Chapter 4, for example, I note that an argument against the possibility that Venus once had oceans has the same structure as an argument for the end of the world (or more precisely, of humankind) advanced by the philosopher John Leslie and inspired by the physicist Brandon Carter’s account of the anthropic principle. In my opinion, both the objection to Venusian oceans and Leslie’s argument assume an untenable view of probability.

Whatever the benefits of space exploration, it also involves a variety of risks. One danger, in particular, seems to be of great importance: the unavoidable connection between space technology and war. This connection is presumably made quite obvious by the terror inflicted upon London in World War II by Wernher von Braun’s V2 rockets, and strengthened by Ronald Reagan’s proposal for a Star Wars defense against the Soviets’ intercontinental ballistic missiles, themselves strong evidence of the evils men fall prey to when reaching for the heavens. We will see in Chapter 9, however, that the connection between space technology and war is not quite that obvious. Its apparent plausibility comes from popular historical interpretations of the relevant episodes, but a closer look fails to support the claim that the connection is unavoidable. Moreover, space technology may prove to be key to the long-term survival of terrestrial life, as Zubrin and others have claimed.

By Chapter 10, it will be clear that the profound practicality of science, via the serendipity that is its natural consequence, provides an adequate response to the social critics. Our new understanding of science in light of space exploration will also set aside the concerns of the ideological critics. Most ideological criticisms stem from purported insights about the relationship between human beings and the environment of the Earth – insights such as the balance of nature, the wisdom of non-interference with natural processes, and so on. But as we will see, such insights do not withstand scrutiny. Moreover, to offer a strong argument, the ideological critics need a global understanding of the Earth’s environment. But as I explain again in this final chapter, that global understanding requires the assistance of comparative planetology and space technology. To meet their ultimate goals, and our obligation to future generations, they would do well to ally themselves with the “big science” they so often deride.



[i] Robert Zubrin’s seminal ideas about exploration will be discussed in several other chapters, particularly in Chapter 7.